On Having No Clue

Let’s suppose you’re trying to figure out if something is going to be A or B, but you have no clue.

What probability should you assign to each option?

Some people might say that you should assign 5050. After all, the argument goes, if you assigned 4060 or 6040, well it sure sounds like you’re favoring one option over another.

That’s a very persuasive argument, but unfortunately, it’s more complicated than that.

It may be the case that A splits into two options A1 and A2 where again we have no clue whether A1 is more likely than A2 or how these compare to B. In which case, the same argument would suggest that we should go with 33/​33/​33 (rounding down).

This seems to be a contradiction. What should we make of this?

First of all, I think we should accept that this exact process of reasoning leads to a contradiction. There’s nothing fancy going on here. No dubious steps that could give us an out.

We tried to say that if we had no clue that the logical thing to do is to assign equal probability to each option, we forgot that we were implicitly assuming that we should favor our particular way of carving up probability space.

In other words, we did need a clue after all. So what kind of clue is this exactly?

Well, surely in order to be justified in carving up the space a particular way, we’d need to have a reason to believe that each possibility is equally likely a priori.

Sadly, this is circular. We wanted to defend equal probabilities by asserting that our way of carving up the space was reasonable, but then we tried to assert that it was reasonable by claiming that each possibility had equal probability.

The problem is that we are making an assumption, but rather than owning it, we’re trying to deny that we’re making any assumption at all, ie. “I’m not assuming a priori A and B have equal probability based on my subjective judgement, I’m using the principle of indifference”. Roll to disbelieve.

Contra Descartes, if you start with nothing, you can’t get anywhere.