Decision Theory Paradox: Answer Key

As promised, I’m posting the answers to the exercises I wrote in the decision theory post.

Exercise 1: Prove that if the population consists of TDT agents and DefectBots, then a TDT agent will cooperate precisely when at least one of the other agents is also TDT. (Difficulty: 1 star.)

With the utility function specified (i.e. the shortsighted one that only cares about immediate children), the TDT agent’s decision can be deduced from simple superrationality concerns; that is, if any other TDT agents are present with analogous utility functions, then their decisions will be identical. Thus if a TDT faces off against 2 DefectBots, it chooses between 0 children (for C) and 2 children (for D), and thus it defects. If it faces off against a TDT and a DefectBot, it chooses between 3 children (for C) and 2 children (for D), so it cooperates. And if it faces off against two other TDTs, it chooses between 6 children (for C) and 2 children (for D), so it cooperates. (EDIT: It’s actually not that simple after all- see Douglas Knight’s comment and the ensuing discussion.)

Exercise 2: Prove that if a very large population starts with equal numbers of TDTs and DefectBots, then the expected population growth in TDTs and DefectBots is practically equal. (If Omega samples with replacement– assuming that the agents don’t care about their exact copy’s children– then the expected population growth is precisely equal.) (Difficulty: 2 stars.)

For the sake of simplicity, we’ll consider only the parenthetical case. (The interested reader can see that if sampled without replacement, the figures will differ by a factor on the order of one divided by the population.) There are four cases to consider when Omega picks a trio: it includes 0, 1, 2 or 3 TDT agents, with probability 18, 38, 38 and 18 respectively. The first case results in 6 DefectBots being returned; the second results in 4 DefectBots and 2 TDTs; the third results in 8 DefectBots and 6 TDTs; the last results in 18 TDTs. Weighting and adding the cases, each “side” has expected population growth of 5.25 agents in that round.

Exercise 3: Prove that if the initial population consists of TDTs and DefectBots, then the ratio of the two will (with probability 1) tend to 1 over time. (Difficulty: 3 stars.)

This is a bit tricky; note that the expected population growth is higher for the more populous side! However, the expected fertility of each agent is higher on the less populous side, and thus its share grows proportionally. (Think of the demographics of a small minority with high fertility- while they won’t have as many total children as the rest of the population, their proportion of the population will increase.)

For very large populations, we can model the fraction of DefectBots as a differential equation, and we will show that this differential equation has a single stable attractive equilibrium at 12. Let N be the total population at a given moment, and x (in (0,1)) the fraction of that population consisting of DefectBots. Then we let P(x)=6x3+12x2(1-x)+24x(1-x)2 and Q(x)=6x2(1-x)+18x(1-x)2+18(1-x)3 denote the expected population growth for DefectBots and TDTs, respectively (these numbers are arrived at in the same way we calculated Exercise 2 in the special case x=1/​2), and note that the “difference quotient” between the old and new fractions of the population comes out to ((1-x)P(x)-xQ(x))/​(N+P(x)+Q(x)). If we consider this to be x’ and study the differential equation (with an extra parameter N for the current population), we see that indeed, x has a stable equilibrium when the expected fertilities are equal (that is, P(x)/​x = Q(x)/​(1-x)) at x=1/​2, and that x steadily increases for x<1/​2 and steadily decreases for x>1/​2.

I’ll admit that this isn’t a rigorous proof, but it’s the correct heuristic calculation; increased formalism only makes it more difficult to communicate.

Exercise 4: If the initial population consists of CliqueBots, DefectBots and TDTs in any proportion, then the ratio of both others to CliqueBots approaches 0 (with probability 1). (Difficulty: 4 stars.)

We can model this as a differential equation in the two-dimensional region {x+y+z=1: 0<x,y,z<1}, and as in Exercise 3 a stable equilibrium is a point at which the three expected fertilities are equal. At this point, it’s worthwhile to note that you can calculate expected fertilities more simply by, for a given agent, counting only its individual fertility given the possible other two partners in the PD. If we let x, y and z denote the proportions of DefectBots, TDTs and CliqueBots, respectively, and let P, Q, and R denote their respective fertilities as functions of x,y and z, then we get

  • P(x,y,z)=2x2+4xy+8y2+4xz+4yz+2z2

  • Q(x,y,z)=2x2+6xy+6y2+4xz+6yz+2z2

  • R(x,y,z)=2x2+4xy+8y2+4xz+4yz+6z2

It is simple to show that if we set x=0, then R>Q for all {(y,z):y+z=1,0<y,z<1}; that is, CliqueBots beat TDTs completely when DefectBots are not present. It is even simpler to show that they beat DefectBots entirely when TDTs are not present. It is a bit more complicated when all three are together: there is a tiny unstable region near (3/​4,1/​4,0) where Q>R, but the proportions drift out of this region as y gains against x, and they do not return; the stable equilibrium is at (0,0,1) as claimed.

Finally,

Problem: The setup looks perfectly fair for TDT agents. So why do they lose? (Difficulty: 2+3i stars.)

As explained in the consequentialism post, we’ve handicapped TDT by giving our agents shortsighted utility functions. If they instead care about distant descendants (let’s say that Omega is only running the experiment finitely many times, either for a fixed number of tournaments or until the population reaches a certain number), then (unless it’s known that the experiment is soon to end) the gains in population made by dominating the demographics will overwhelm the immediate gains of letting a DefectBot or CliqueBot take advantage of the agent. Growing almost 6-fold each time one’s selected (or occupying a larger fraction of the fixed final population) will justify the correct decision, essentially via the more complicated calculations we’ve done above.