Weighting the probability of being a mind by the quantity of the matter composing the computer that calculates that mind

TL;DR by lavalamp: Treating “computers running minds” as discrete objects might cause a paradox in probability calculations that involve self-location. “The probability of being a certain mind” is probably an extensive physical quantity, i.e. rises proportionally to the size of the physical system doing the associated computations.

There are two computers simulating two minds. At some time, one of the minds is being shown a red light, and the other one is shown a green one (call this “Situation 1”). Conditioned on you being one of the minds, what is the probability you should assign to seeing red?

Naively, the answer seems to be 12, which comes from assigning being each of the minds an equal probability. If one had three computers and showed two of them a red light and the third one a green one, the probability would be calculated as 23, even if the red-seeing computers will be in exactly the same computational state at all times (call this “Situation 2”).

However, I think that taking this point of view leads to paradoxes.

An example: Consider an electrical circuit made of (ideal) wires, resistors, capacitors and transistors (sufficient in principle to build a computer); the supply voltage comes from outside of the circuit considered. Under assumptions regarding the physical implementation of this circuit that do not restrict the possible circuit diagrams, it is possible to split the matter composing it into two part that both comprise working circuits reproducing the original circuit’s behavior independently of the other part, in an analogous fashion to how the Ebborian’s brains are split.* To clarify, what I have in mind is cutting up the wires and resistors orthogonally to their cross-sections—after the splitting, equivalent wires should be on equivalent potentials at the same time, but the currents flowing will be reduced by some factor.

Now imagine the circuit is a computer, simulating the mind that is going to see red in Situation 1 (the mind that will see green still exists). If one splits the circuit as described, one suddenly ends up with two circuits simulating the same mind, i.e. Situation 2 (let’s imagine that the computers are split before they are turned on for the first time, so that stream-of-consciousness-considerations will not influence the calculated probability, like e.g. Deda answering 12 to Yu’el’s question in the linked article). However, it is not clear how far the circuit components need to be apart from each other so that they should be considered “split”. I.e., if one fixes a direction in which the circuits are moved apart and then defines P(d) as “the probability one should assign to seeing red, as a function of the distance by which the circuits have been moved apart), P(0) would be 12 and P(∞) would be 23 in the naive model, but there seems to be no intuitive way how the function should look like in between.

I think that therefore, it is more plausible that a way closer to the correct one to calculate the probability of having one mind’s experiences involves somehow weighting this probability by the amount (maybe mass or electron count) of matter that calculates the mind. If one does this, after splitting, the matter comprising each of the parts will add up exactly to the matter of the original circuit, so P(d) would be constant over all distances.

What do you think?

*Namely, the resistors could be full cylinders with the wires protruding along the axes—one could then split them by a plane surface surface that includes the cylinder’s axis and would end up with two resistors that have twice the resistance.

The capacitors could look exactly like in this picture and could then be split up along a plane that includes the wires, so that the capacitance is halved.

The transistors could look exactly like in this picture (being homogeneous in the z-direction), and be split up in half across a plane that is parallel to the picture shown).

If one does all of those splittings and splits up the wires so that the parts of each electronic component are connected in the same way as the original circuit was connected, and then operates the resulting circuits with the same supply voltage as one operated the original circuit, the voltages of all wires will always be the same as in the original circuit, and currents will be halved.